An version of this article was printed in Humanism Ireland, May-June, Vol. 152 (2015)
Until the second half of the twentieth century, there was little disagreement, at least within mainstream western thought, over the standard for human death. Death occurs when the heart has stopped beating and breathing has come to an end. The issue of whether or not someone is dead was generally held to be a simple question of fact. However, scientific and technological advances since the late 1950s—where the heart and breathing of patients could be artificially maintained by ventilators for weeks or months after all functions of the brain are irreversibly lost—have made the whole question more complex.
As a result of this, the Harvard Brain Death Committee—which
included a number of medical professionals, lawyers and theologians—was
established; in their landmark 1968 report they argued that the clinical standard
of diagnosing death should be when the whole brain, or brainstem, has
permanently ceased to function. The Committee, in other words, proposed a neurological
requirement for determining death rather than the traditional cardiopulmonary
one. Those who met the new criterion were now considered ‘brain-dead’. The redefinition
also allowed doctors to turn off life-support when patients’ brains have ceased
to function.
Following this, most developed
nations—with the notable exception of Japan—have medically redefined death to
something more closely in line with the Committee’s criterion. In Ireland and
Britain, for instance, the definition involves death of
the brainstem. Rather surprisingly,
there was very little opposition to this widespread change—even the Vatican went
along with it. Nevertheless, there are
some who remain sceptical: they argue that the concept of brain-death rests on
shaky foundations, and it permits patients to be declared as dead before they
really are.
Perhaps none of
this is surprising—seeing that it’s now generally accepted that the main driving
factors were pragmatic in nature. It was, by and large, a convenient way around
the problem of overcrowding in hospital wards (not to mention the enormous costs
involved) that materialised, consisting of patients on mechanical respirators
with no prospect of recovery. By stating that brain-dead patients are dead,
doctors no longer had to hold off until patients’ hearts stop beating before turning
off respirators. The redefinition also
enabled organs to be removed
from patients whose brains had ceased to function; patients whose hearts
continue to beat due to artificial respirators usually have healthier organs—ones
that are less likely to deteriorate—if removed before the body has ceased to
function. The redefinition, therefore, allowed surgeons to acquire a larger
supply of viable organs for transplantation. Considering these points, we can
see why some might view the redefinition as a legal fiction, invoked by
authorities to get round a number of practical problems that have materialised due
to the advances in medical technology.
A number of problems
with recognising brain-death as death of the human organism have also been identified—both
empirically and conceptually. To begin with, it assumes that when the whole brain
has ceased to function, that is sufficient for the human organism to be
declared dead. But why think of the brain as so important? (It’s worth mentioning
also that some scholars (e.g., here and here) have pointed out that in some brain-dead patients minor brain functions
often continue, such as the supply of various hormones that help modulate a number
of bodily functions. In terms of whole
brain death, does it matter that some functions remain?)
Proponents of the
brain-death standard maintain that cessation of integrated functioning of the
organism is sufficient for someone to be classified as brain-dead. However, the
paediatric neurologist, Alan Shewmon, has pointed out in a series of papers that some integrated functioning can occur
without any contribution at all from the brain; for instance, in patients who
are declared clinically brain dead, somatically integrated functions—such as
homoeostasis, energy balance, wound healing, the fighting of infections, the proportional
growth of brain dead children, and a number of others—are possible. Shewmon argues that the brain should be seen as
more of an enhancer than an essential integrator of
bodily functions.
Proponents may insist
that critical integrative functioning,
that is controlled by the brain, is still essential in order to sustain life. After
brain-death occurs, circulation of the blood and respiration are only possible
with the aid of an artificial respirator, but nothing more than an externally
supported but functioning body is insufficient for the presence of life. Instances
like this, they claim, merely present a false appearance of life. The brain, it
seems, is the only possible primary integrator. This suggests, according to
defenders of the brain-death standard, that the human organism is deemed alive only
if a satisfactory amount of functioning is integrated by the brain. But what
should count as a satisfactory amount? And,
more fundamentally, why is it not possible for a human organism to be genuinely
declared alive in cases where significant functions are only supported by artificial
means? The philosopher David DeGrazia,
for instance, points out that what’s
important is not that the brain is maintaining the body’s functioning, but that
there’s actually something there doing it.
This notion is further
challenged by considering patients suffering from extreme cases of locked-in syndrome—where there is significant, though
not complete, destruction of the brain. Locked-in
sufferers may be fully conscious (they are clearly alive!), but they may
exhibit no more integrated functioning than brain-dead patients. The integrated
functioning of a locked-in sufferer will have to be sustained by intensive
medical support in order for him to survive, since the brain cannot do any
integrating. According to brain-death theorists, the brain-dead patient
is dead, but I doubt any of them would be willing to say the extreme locked-in
patient is also dead.
Proponents of the
brain-death standard will of course point out that the locked-in patient is
still conscious, while the brain-death patient is not. Yet even if the capacity
for consciousness is recognised as the underlying difference between the two
cases, we will nevertheless have to abandon the condition that the brain must
integrate the organism’s functioning for someone to be declared alive. Simply because
someone’s integrated functioning is being externally supported—as the example
of the extreme locked-in patient demonstrates—cannot be a sufficient reason for
thinking that she is dead.
In light of this, some
scientists and philosophers have abandoned the whole brain-death criterion and
have proposed something even more radical in its place. The biological death of
the human organism, according to this offering, ought to be defined as “the irreversible
cessation of the capacity for consciousness”. This concept of death is usually
referred to as ‘higher brain-death’ or ‘cortical death’. Proponents of this view argue that
once the capacity or potential for consciousness is lost, one thereby dies. For
this reason, it is permissible to withdraw feeding tubes and to remove organs
for transplantation (assuming prior consent is given) after consciousness is
irreversibly lost. The higher brain-death criterion, for the most part, still considers
it paramount to determine whether or not someone is alive, as its proponents maintain
that it’s wrong to intentionally take innocent human life.
To
be sure, many will regard the criterion for higher brain-death as highly dubious.
For instance, patients who lapse into a persistent vegetative state (PVS) will meet this standard. The
destruction of the cerebral cortex denies those in a PVS the capacity or
potential for consciousness, but, nevertheless, they can often continue to
breathe and sustain other vital functions, with little mechanical assistance,
as the brainstem remains intact and functional; some of those in a PVS can also
be maintained for several years, and sometimes even decades, by artificial
feeding. To declare that PVS patients are not actually alive, as proponents of
the higher brain-death criterion do, might be a bit too much for most people to
digest.
A more fundamental
problem with the higher brain-death standard is that it assumes the irreversible
loss of consciousness is sufficient for the death of a human being in the
biological sense. However, it’s generally acknowledged that young foetuses and
certain anencephalic infants are living human organisms, despite
the fact they are not conscious. If we accept that beings like this can live
and die, then it seems we have to accept that there are some living human
organisms that don’t possess the capacity for consciousness. On that account,
and contrary to what higher brain-death proponents argue, having no capacity or
potential for consciousness cannot be a sufficient condition for the death of
the human organism. Seeing that anencephalic infants have a similar status
to patients in a PVS, it seems rather odd, then, to regard the former as alive
and the latter as dead.
In order to avoid this problem, one could deny that anencephalic infants
are living beings as well. This move seems implausible, though, since they have each
of the biological functions and capacities that ordinary human infants have (apart
from those dealing with consciousness). On top of that, I don’t believe many
people (including proponents of the higher-brain dead criterion) would be comfortable
with the idea of the cremation or burial of spontaneous breathing anencephalic
infants or adults in a PVS.
If the whole brain-death and higher brain-death
standards are abandoned, what are we left with? Some claim the problem
needs to be understood in a different way altogether. Instead of focusing on the question
“at what point does the human organism die?” we should ask “what actually matters?”
The philosopher Jeff McMahan argues that when the irreversible loss of the capacity for
consciousness occurs, the person ceases to exist, while the human organism may continue
to live. According to this view, the human organism does not necessarily die
when the brain has ceased to function, but only when there’s cessation of
breathing and heartbeat.
The question of when a human being loses moral status,
McMahan claims, is not necessarily synonymous with the question of when the
biological organism dies. Persons clearly have moral status: they are
conscious, they have the capacity for self-control and autonomy, they can
experience pleasure and pain, they have memories of the past and a sense of the
future. On the other hand, living human organisms, where consciousness has been
irreversibly lost, do not possess any of these attributes, so, therefore, they
don’t matter in the same way as persons do. A similar view is expressed by
Peter Singer in Rethinking Life & Death (1994): “The fact that a being is human, and alive, does not
in itself tell us whether it is wrong to take that being’s life”. Rather than proposing
contrived definitions of death, it’s more appropriate (and honest) to say that
once consciousness has been irreversibly lost, it may well be permissible to
withdraw external life support and remove organs, whether the human organism is
deemed alive or not. (Of course, questions of prior consent will still have to
be considered).
Once we accept that it’s consciousness—and not life—that
gives us moral status, we will no longer be tempted to conjure up redefinitions
of human death. Needless to say, this position stands contrary to the principle
of the sanctity of human
life, a doctrine than many people today still hold
as unconditional and universal. But can, and should, atheists and humanists continue to uphold this doctrine? Can mere membership of the species Homo sapiens alone, irrespective of other characteristics, be
sufficient for someone to acquire full moral status? The principle of the
sanctity of human life is a relic of Christianity (i.e., that humans are
separate and intrinsically unique from the rest of creation), and it persists in our secular world
today. It seems to me, however, that progress
in technology and medicine are making it much more difficult to sustain this way
of thinking.
Comments
Post a Comment