A version of this article was printed in Humanism Ireland, Jan-Feb, Vol. 144 (2014)
About half a century ago, homosexuality was illegal everywhere in the world, with the exception of a dozen or so countries. It wasn't until the 1960s and 1970s that the gay rights movement, supported by the principle of human rights, accelerated. Today homosexuality is legal in about 120 countries—though still banned in several places—and some have even moved towards legally recognising same-sex marriage. In 2001 the first laws enabling same-sex marriage occurred in the Netherlands; since then, fourteen other countries (including Argentina, Belgium, and South Africa) and several other regional jurisdictions have also introduced same-sex marriage.
About half a century ago, homosexuality was illegal everywhere in the world, with the exception of a dozen or so countries. It wasn't until the 1960s and 1970s that the gay rights movement, supported by the principle of human rights, accelerated. Today homosexuality is legal in about 120 countries—though still banned in several places—and some have even moved towards legally recognising same-sex marriage. In 2001 the first laws enabling same-sex marriage occurred in the Netherlands; since then, fourteen other countries (including Argentina, Belgium, and South Africa) and several other regional jurisdictions have also introduced same-sex marriage.
Homosexuality in
the Republic of Ireland was finally decriminalised in June 1993. Despite a slow
start, the trajectory of gay rights moved rather fast, with the Civil Partnership and Certain
Rights and Obligations of Cohabitants Act 2010 introduced in January 2011, granting same-sex
couples the right to register their relationship as a civil partnership; in
April 2013 the Constitutional Convention—formed by the Government assigned with considering
wide-ranging changes to the Irish constitution—voted in favour of legalising
for same-sex marriage by a margin of 79 percent. As a result, in November it was announced by the
Government to hold a referendum on gay marriage before the summer of
2015. An opinion poll taken around the
same time as the Cabinet's announcement suggests that 76 percent of voters support
the introduction of same sex marriage. This proportion may not be as high when
it comes to a referendum as previous polls suggest, but there’s still a very
strong chance a majority of the electorate would vote in favour of gay and
lesbian marriage.*
In spite of committed
opponents of gay marriage acknowledging the fact that the pendulum of popular
opinion is now swinging against them, they continue to challenge the mainstream
liberal consensus. It would, of course, be spurious to say that gay and lesbian
marriage is legitimate because most people believe that it is; at one
time, almost everyone believed that the sun revolves around the earth, but they
were wrong. Most people, at present, seem to believe same-sex marriage should
be made legal, but perhaps they are also mistaken. So, are there any valid
arguments against same-sex marriage? Various socially conservative and
religious commentators have advanced a number of reasons to defend the
traditional paradigm of marriage. Let us consider some of these.
It is often said
that same-sex marriage is unnatural. Marriage by its essence is a male-female
union, and to advocate in other respects is the equivalent of wanting to draw a
squared circle. Equally, it is questionable whether we can really call
heterosexual marriage ‘natural’ either: traditional marriage, some regard, to
be nothing more than an artificially constructed patriarchal socioeconomic
institution, historically convenient for those who want to control the lives of
women within family and social life.
You might say
there’s nothing natural about marriage per se, but the traditional ideal of
lifelong commitment of one man and one woman, for the purpose of intimacy and
child rearing, is the keystone to stability and is therefore something that’s
worth preserving. Yet, the American philosopher Martha Nussbaum, in her
2009 Dessent article, reminds us that the “golden age of martial purity” is a
mistaken ideal: “many societies,” she says, “have embraced forms of polygamy,
informal or common-law marriage, and sequential monogamy.”
In ancient Greece,
for instance, married men regularly had socially accepted sexual relationships
with male and female prostitutes. Divorce was also widespread in ancient Rome,
and marriages were “typically not monogamous,” where men were likely to have
sexual relations with male and female slaves and prostitutes. In more recent
times, to be sure, social standards of monogamy were more widespread, but it’s
doubtful whether these norms actually reflected social reality. It’s difficult
to examine the reality of marital conflict and break-up, Nussbaum argues,
because almost all marriages were not formally terminated until very recently.
On top of that, before divorce was a legal possibility, women often had to
tolerate “bad marriages, with adultery, neglect, even with domestic violence.”
Based on this, it seems difficult to contemplate an epoch of ubiquitous
heterosexual martial purity and rapport as anything other than a
fairytale.
Another objection
is the argument that the main purpose of marriage is procreation and the
nurturing of children. Marriage, in line with its quintessence, is an
institution that works for these objectives and it is in our collective
interest to confine marriage to potentially procreative couples. Reproduction
cannot arise in a homosexual marriage, so accordingly we should not grant it
the same status as a heterosexual one. But hardly anyone thinks marriage should
only be limited to couples where procreation is probable. If we prohibit
same-sex marriage for this reason, it would seem to follow that we should also
prohibit heterosexual marriage if one, or both, of the partners is infertile,
or where a couple has no intention of child-bearing.
One response to
this—put forward by Sherif Girgis, Ryan T. Anderson and Robert P. George in
their book, What Is Marriage? Man and
Woman: A Defense (2012)—is that marriage in the latter cases would be
legitimate because the couple can still accomplish a “comprehensive bodily
union”—coitus—a function that can work towards a common biological
end—reproduction. Put simply, marriage requires a comprehensive bodily union
and only coitus can achieve such a union. This explains, rather conveniently,
why it is reasonable to allow infertile heterosexuals to lawfully marry, but
not homosexuals. It’s possible for same-sex couples to engage in sexual
activity together, Ryan, Anderson and George contend, but such unions are not
comprehensive, given that coitus is not possible. But then again why should we
accept coitus as a significant and obligatory provision for marriage? It seems
quite arbitrary (and to my mind, rather odd) that a comprehensive marriage can
only be accomplished through penis-vagina sex.
Even if we accept
this inference, how can we understand the case of a heterosexual couple were
one partner is seriously paralysed and cannot perform coitus? Most people, I
presume, would accept marriage in this case as admissible. It would seem inconsistent
not to allow lesbian couples to marry purely because coitus cannot be achieved,
while permitting straight couples to marry when coitus also isn't feasible.
To evade this inconsistency, one could always say that heterosexual marriages
are not comprehensive in the absence of coitus either, but I doubt there are
many that would be prepared to endorse this position.
Someone might
disapprove of gay marriage for less abstract reasons. An objection variously
expressed is that children get on best with their biological parents and gay
parents are not as good for them. However, is this really the case? The
evidence supporting the claim is not strong. The American Psychological
Association (APA)
recognises findings from several studies on same-sex parenting and concludes
“that there is no scientific evidence that parenting effectiveness is related
to parental sexual orientation.” Further, the “well-being of children are
unrelated to parental sexual orientation and that the children of lesbian and
gay parents are as likely as those of heterosexual parents to flourish.”
Perhaps we should
doubt whether parenting has any significant impact on children at all. The
psychologist Judith Rich Harris, author of The Nurture Assumption: Why
Children Turn Out the Way They Do (1998), argues that there is not much evidence to support
the claim that the way parents rear their children has long-term effects on their
personality, intelligence or mental well being. Basing her research on twin
studies, Harris contends that a child’s outcome is more likely to result from
genes the parents provide and other environmental and cultural factors, like
her peer group and chance. In The Blank Slate: The Modern
Denial of Human Nature (2002), the
evolutionary psychologist Steven Pinker has also pointed out that many studies
that look at correlations between what parents do and how their children turn
out, simply assume there’s a causal relation without really considering
possible genetic factors. Not everyone agrees with Harris or Pinker’s thesis
that parenting has minimal influence, but perhaps this is due to the ostensibly
discouraging conclusions arrived at, than the actual merits of what they claim.
It nevertheless magnifies an already mounting challenge to those who argue that
children get on best when raised with their biological parents as one of the
central reasons to oppose gay marriage and same-sex parenting.
Having said that,
say convincing evidence did emerge, showing that children do, in fact, turn out
best when raised with their biological parents: would that be an ample reason
to deny same-sex marriage? I’m not convinced it would, as it is based on a
logical non sequitur. Suppose a study showed that children of rich parents turn
out better off than children of poor parents, and that children of parents from
one ethnic group turn out better, on average, than children from another ethnic
group: would this give legitimate grounds to refuse certain groups of people
from marrying or raising children? I think most would be appalled if we
prevented couples from marrying on the basis of their salary or ethnicity.
In the same way, I
think it is equally wrong to discriminate against couples based on their sexual
orientation, even if it could be shown that children, on average, fair out
better within heterosexual marriages. We don’t discriminate against the marital
and parenting rights of couples based on class, ethnicity, occupation, IQ and
so forth, even if we know variations on the outcome of children can exist due
to those factors. If individual couples can maintain a reasonable quality of
care, irrespective of their identity, we should see it as acceptable for them
to rear and nurture children.
It is often said
that a child deserves the right to a mother and a father—preferably his two
biological parents. Those who say this, however, do not explain why a child’s
right is violated if he’s not raised by his biological mother and father. Maybe
in a perfect world this condition would be preferable, but quite often children
are brought up by adoptive parents, grandparents, older siblings, or with just
one parent. It seems to make more sense to say a child has the right to
be raised in a stable, happy environment, with at least one responsible adult,
than to say, in the more abstract sense, that he has the right to be raised by
his two biological parents. We cannot assume the latter case will always be
more desirable or in the child’s best interest.
Someone might still
object to marriage equality because the integration of lesbian and gay couples into the institution of marriage could have adverse and unintended
consequences on society. It would change society, to be sure, but where is the
evidence to suggest it would make things worse? On the contrary, there are a
number of reasons to believe it would actually enrich society. To be identified
as gay or lesbian, until quite recently, carried a huge stigma and many decided
(as some still do) to conceal their true identity: equal marriage opportunity
shows that we are prepared to move away from routine homophobia and
prejudice—which has resulted in bad outcomes for many—to a position where the
state is prepared to give equal marital status and inclusiveness to gays and
lesbians.
Moreover, there
would be more couples willing to adopt and this would be in the interest of
many children: instead of living inside state institutions, a child could be
adopted by a gay or lesbian couple willing to give her love and support. Gay
marriage may, paradoxically, result in less same-sex couples
looking after children. In a recent article for The Philosophers’ Magazine, John Corvino argues that where same-sex marriage is more
accepted, “fewer would feel pressure to enter heterosexual relationships for
which they are not suited, and thus fewer children would experience the breakup
of such marriages.” And if we’re interested in child welfare, Corvino
continues, “fewer divorces is surely a good thing.”
Another objection
sometimes invoked is that the advancement of civil partnerships to the prestige
of marriage fundamentally redefines its meaning, and thus threatens to diminish
the value of existing marriages. This sounds unconvincing though: many same-sex
couples want to get married for similar reasons to others, and I fail to see
how one’s marriage could be tarnished where it was discovered that a gay couple
moved into her neighbourhood. Indeed, Nussbaum points out that
“[c]onvicted felons, divorced parents who fail to pay child support, people
with a record of domestic violence or emotional abuse, delinquent taxpayers,
drug abusers, rapists, murderers, racists, anti-Semites, [and] other bigots”
are all legally entitled to get married, once it’s to someone of the opposite
sex. Opponents of gay marriage, in this way, will have to explain why the
marriage of a law abiding gay couple does more to discredit the institution
than the inclusion of paedophiles, sadists and masochists in heterosexual
marriages.
Someone might
defend current marriage practices purely on the basis of tradition. The union
of one man and one woman, they would say, is a feature of society over the
centuries, something deeply rooted in our present day culture, and that we
should carry on honouring this convention. Yet this argument, it seems, could
equally be used as a justification for same-sex marriage. Seeing that
homosexuality is now widely tolerated and even celebrated, extending marriage
to include gay and lesbian couples, it could be argued, is the best way of
honouring and preserving the tradition.
Some liberal
commentators have also expressed some qualms about the public discourse surrounding
same-sex marriage. In a recent Village article, for
instance, Michael Cronin states that: “[t]he political goal of sexual freedom
[including gay marriage] has been recruited to a reductively one-dimensional
model of progress and modernisation, which serves to validate the prevailing
power structures even while apparently questioning them.” As a result,
“[s]ituating any radical Left perspective on gender and sexuality is
untenable.” Public discourse regarding marriage equality, it is probably fair
to say, is in accordance with existing power structures, yet it still seems
possible for progressive development to emerge through this model. The legalisation
of gay and lesbian marriage will not banish homophobia altogether, and it would
be naïve to see it as a teleological endpoint. We should not expect
gay rights activists, and those concerned with social justice, to rest easily
if, and when, legislation is passed. A more detailed account is probably needed
to fully address these points, but that is beyond the scope of my analysis
here.
Marriage doesn't
exist for one particular purpose and its meaning has continuously evolved
overtime. In modern societies, marriage is plural in its definition and
content: no longer does it just involve shared domestic life and the begetting
and nurturing of children; it also accommodates sexual relations, love and
intimacy, friendship and reciprocated care, concern and commitment. When we
consider all, or some, of these as perfectly valid reasons for straight people
to marry, broadening this vista to include gay and lesbian couples, seems like
the morally right thing to do. Many objections were examined here, but
none give us compelling reason to deny same-sex couples the right to marry; gay
and lesbian partners, in due course, will be legally allowed to marry in
Ireland for sure.
*Note: the second paragraph was slightly updated to include
the government’s intention to hold a referendum in 2015 and the opinion poll
figure that was released in early November 2013.
Comments
Post a Comment